• Welcome to League Of Reason Forums! Please read the rules before posting.
    If you are willing and able please consider making a donation to help with site overheads.
    Donations can be made via here

Newton disproves Darwin?

sophophilo

New Member
arg-fallbackName="sophophilo"/>
A (creationist) friend gave me this article by Ed Dellian and i found it very weird, to say the least...
I'm not quite sure how he managed to suddenly jump from newtons law of motion to the evolution of biological systems... this guy is either too smart or simply dishonest... either way I'm currently unable to debunk him properly...
need help!

The paper as .pdf: http://www.neutonus-reformatus.com/download/dellian_on_the_origin_of_species.pdf
http://www.neutonus-reformatus.com/ It's the last one under "publications". Apparently, this is not his first paper on the subject...


Ed Dellian 14169 Berlin, 19.11.2008

Isaac Newton On the Origin of Species (1713)

Abstract
Isaac Newton's "Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica" of 1687 teaches the originat-
ion of "mutations" of motion by active "forces of nature". In the second edition (1713) of the
"Principia" Newton's editor Roger Cotes (in an "editor's preface") and Newton himself (in a
"Scholium generale") embedded the theory in the much broader context of creation of the
new, ultimately referring to the Creator. Newton's natural "forces" or "causes" relate to this
"First cause", and they are always and only active immaterial principles to activate passive
matter. These invisible generating principles can be known by their observable material ef-
fects according to "analogy", that is the Euclidean geometric proportion theory which New-
ton prefers as a mathematical device in the "Principia". Newton's dualist theory of origination
of motion is at variance with the evolutionists belief in the activity and omnipotency of matter
as a corner-stone of their hypothetical-deductive theory of the origin of species. In short: If
Newton was right, Darwin was wrong.


Introduction
Isaac Newton (1642-1727), about 150 years before Charles Darwin, published a particular
theory on the origin of species. This fact should be known not only to Newton scholars, but
also to theologians and biologists, at least since Christoph Cardinal Schà¶nborn's 2006 Castel
Gandolfo talk "Fides, Ratio, Scientia: The Debate about Evolution" (1). The Cardinal began
by recalling the 1713 publication of Newton's Scholium generale to the second edition of his
famous Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica of 1687. Quoting extensively from
Newton, he showed that, according to the opus quoted, "out of the blind play of chance and
necessity the diversity of natural things cannot arise" and the Cardinal added correctly: "The
theory of evolution that is current today says precisely the opposite" (2). Actually, Newton's
reasoning results in understanding the really existing God as the "First cause", the Creator and
Governor of everything, including all changes of states of everything as effects of secondary
causes depending on the God above all, whose existence always and everywhere Newton calls
an inescapable fact (3).
Even though he did not literally anticipate Darwin's 1859 title "On the Origin of Species" in
his 1713 Scholium generale, Isaac Newton wrote on the very same subject as Darwin - the
origin of variety and variation in nature. But while Darwin tried to explain the phenomena by
empirically identifiable mechanisms, Newton stated that "all that diversity of natural things
2
which we find suited to different times and places could arise from nothing but the ideas and
will of a Being necessarily existing" (4). Newton argued on the basis of a throughout scienti-
fic (i.e. mathematical) general theory of "mutatio", i.e. of the change of phenomena from a
state A to a different state B. The germ of this theory of course concerns the "origin", that is
the how and why of the forthcoming of something really "new" at its very beginning, of some-
thing (some new phenomenon, some new state of being of something) that had never existed
before. Cardinal Schà¶nborn in his 2006 talk did not enter into this problem, but generally re-
ferred to my relevant book "Die Rehabilitierung des Galileo Galilei oder Wie die Wahrheit zu
messen ist" (5). Thoughtlessly he insinuated that Newton might perhaps have deduced his the-
istic statements from a hypothetically presupposed "belief in the Creator (that) makes him see
things in this light". This idea, however, contradicts Newton's scientific method "hypotheses
non fingo" (for this cf. Roger Cotes's and Newton's methodological statements in the follow-
ing paragraph 3). Newton did not introduce "God" as a scientific hypothesis from which to de-
duce some insight into the order of the world. Quite the contrary, his empirical method leads
from a first understanding of the "phaenomena" and their true immaterial causes through a
chain of such causes ultimately to truth, i.e. to God as the "first cause" (6). In the following I
will show some of the considerations that were basic for Newton's theistic view of the "ori-
gin", not only of species, but of everything: a view that encouraged Newton's amanuensis
Samuel Clarke already in 1704 to praise the new natural philosophy from the pulpit of St.
Paul's in London as the only philosophy that harmonises with the truth of Christianity.
1. Newton's paradigm of "origin": The origination of a new state of a body's motion.
It was a common belief in Newton's time that the theory of motion provided the "key of natu-
re" (Colin Maclaurin) (7). In some way, motion, its generation, and its change from one state
to another, seemed to lie at the bottom of all natural phenomena, so that its understanding, and
especially the understanding of the natural generating causes thereof, should yield a most ba-
sic and true causal explanation of the phenomena themselves. Accordingly in his preface to
the "Principia" of 1687 Newton argued that it should be the main task of natural philosophy to
deduce the generating "forces" from the phenomena of motion and then to explain other phe-
nomena by these forces. The "Principia" reflects this view already through its composition in
three books, the first two dedicated to "the motion of bodies", and the third to "the system of
the world", which system Newton explained on the basis of the first two books, i.e. by means
of the principles that form the backbone of his "theory of motion", as he developed it in these
two books.
3
1.1. Which are these principles? In short they are: 1) Motion of material bodies is a change of
place in space and time that basically proceeds harmonically (i.e. according to the geometric
proportionality of space and time) in a uniform, straightlined manner. 2) By a careful investi-
gation into the conditions of its very beginning ("ipso motus initio") (8), this real spatio-tem-
poral motion, though not directly observable, can be mathematically determined, and can be
distinguished from rest as well as from only apparent motion, according to certain reasonable
principles, or "laws of motion". 3) The main contents of these laws consists in understanding
by analogy (i.e. by means of Euclid's geometric proportion theory) the invisbile generating
active "causes" of motion, the so-called forces of nature. 4) Causal generation of motion is al-
ways a generation of uniform straightlined motion, not continually, but step by step, i.e. as
"change" of an existing state of motion or rest into another such state in geometric proportion
to its generating cause, that is to the invisible "force" impressed on the body, no matter if this
non-material force "is impressed all at once or successively by degrees" (9). (5) "Accelerated"
or "decelerated" motion, i.e. a motion the velocity of which increases or decreases in the cour-
se of time, is accordingly also not generated continuously, but rather it changes step by step,
in proportion to its generating active cause, i.e. the immaterial or spiritual "force" impressed
on the moving body.
1.2. It is evident that these principles are not those of "classical or Newtonian mechanics" of
the textbooks all around the world. As a matter of fact, the non-geometric classical mechanics
of the schools cannot correctly be ascribed to Newton. It is well known, at least to historians
of science, that Newton's theory, like Galileo's based on the geometric theory of proportions,
on the "analogy of nature" (10), and on a dualism (i.e. a spirit-matter interaction) of non ma-
terial, unobservable generating active "forces of nature", and generated observable ("materi-
al") motion, underwent a radical change during the 18th century. This change is sometimes
called a "positivistic interpretation" (Paolo Casini) (11). Actually it removed the philosophical
feature of this geometric-synthetic theory and made it an arithmetical and analytical technical
tool. This transformation, however, meant a most fundamental change of paradigms: from
Newton's synthesis to Leibnizian analysis, from Newton's geometry to Descartes' and Leib-
niz's arithmetic and algebra, from Newton's analogy of nature to Leibnizian equivalence of
cause and effect, from a neo-platonic Christian dualism of "spirit" (force) and "matter" (mot-
ion of bodies) to materialistic-atheistic monism. This change began in 1637 with Descartes'
work on the reduction of geometry to algebra. Somewhat later, the German philosopher G.W.
4
Leibniz, in order to advance Descartes' mathematical work, explicitly reduced geometric pro-
portions to arithmetic-algebraic equations that no longer represented an equivalence of rela-
tions between different things, but rather an equivalence of things themselves, even of things
like "cause" and "effect" that had been considered different entities so far. The result of this
operation was based not on Newton's principles, but on his philosophical antipode's Leibniz
"first axiom of mechanics", the identification of cause and effect ("causa aequat effectum"),
which made causes indistinguishable from their allegedly "equal" effects. Thus began the de-
cline of Newton's research program: To detect the transcendent forces of nature through in-
vestigation of the phenomena of motion, and then, by means of these forces, to causally ex-
plain other phenomena as effects thereof (12). As a result of the general acceptance of Leib-
niz's and Kant's reductionist program, however, Charles Darwin and others mistook material
effects for originating "causes". Today's evolutionists cannot but imagine "natural causes" as
material, observable phenomena, so that e.g. "mutation" (i.e. the effective appearing of some-
thing new), and "selection" (the effective elimination of the "unfit") are understood as materi-
al causes or "mechanisms" of evolution. Any research that would not a priori deny the exist-
ence of immaterial or transcendent causes (such as e.g. the will of living beings, not to speak
of the will of God) is now spurned as a non-scientific, irrational venture into "supernatural"
regions. Consequently, today's natural science appears not only in a materialistic-atheistic
garb, but is based on the philosophy of materialism (often glossed over as "naturalism"), and
even intrinsically identical with it. From Newton's point of view evolutionists, so long as they
persevere in the restricted realm of material effects and dogmatically refuse to accept even the
possibility of non-material entities, will never successfully identify a true originating cause of
anything, because of the absolute immateriality and transcendence of any causes.
1.3. The above-mentioned principles of Newton's theory of motion and natural philosophy
show what one learns by concentrating not on secondary literature, but on the works of Isaac
Newton himself, mainly on his "Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica" of 1687, 2nd
edition 1713. I learned those principles when in the 1980ies translating Newton's opus mag-
num from his Latin into German. My aim was to make available for the first time a reliable
German edition of the "Principia" which among German scholars (mathematicians, physicists,
philosophers) was as well known as the Holy Bible, that is, only by name, not in its contents.
What I consider a most important result is the fact that Newton teaches "generation", or
should we say "creation" of motion, not as a continuous process that, even though initially
5
perhaps "created" by some cause, from then on should emerge, so to speak, "by itself", that is,
continually in time, without any further intervention of a generating principle. Rather he in-
sists on a stepwise creation which, for every single step, requires a new activity to create it,
i.e. a new generating "force". This "discrete" paradigm of generation of motion can clearly be
understood in Newton's explanation of the "free fall" of bodies: "Corpus cadente, gravitas
uniformis, singulis temporis particulis aequalibus aequaliter agendo, imprimit vires aequales
in corpus illud, et velocitates aequales generat. Et tempore toto vim totam imprimit, et veloci-
tatem totam generat tempori proportionalem." English, according to I. Bernard Cohen and
Anne Whitman: "When a body falls, uniform gravity, by acting equally in individual equal
particles of time, impresses equal forces upon that body and generates equal velocities, and in
the total time it impresses a total force and generates a total velocity proportional to the time"
(13). Evidently, the process of "free fall" according to Newton is a discrete or quantised pro-
cess, the result of which, at any time, must be understood as a sum of discretely generated fi-
nite parts of velocity, every discrete step newly generated in every single "equal particle of ti-
me", which, by the way, shows the quantisation of time (14).
1.4. Newton's message then is: There exists no continuously "accelerating force" in nature to
produce "accelerated motion". There is no continuous emergence of motion in nature (15).
And generally spoken (since "generation of motion" means only an example of the generation
of everything, i.e. of "generation itself", or of "creation"): Nothing in nature emerges continu-
ously ("by itself"). Every individual new "state" of something, which state differs by novelty
from a former state of that something, must individually be generated, or created, as an effect
of an individual cause, or generating "force". This cause is not an equivalent of its effect, ra-
ther causes and effects are basically different entities: the effect being an observable pheno-
menon, the cause being an unobservable, transcendent principle which, however, always ob-
eys a rational geometric proportion to its generated effect. Consequently this cause represents
a measurable entity of its own, namely a truly creative force that is able to generate in space
and time as its effect something new, something that never had existed before. Of course this
concept of generation of the "new" is one of a creatio continua, and also a concept of creatio
ex nihilo. The transition from a state A of "something" to a different state B means that there
must exist a difference, that is, something real must exist in the state B that did not exist in the
previous state A. So the process of generation of a new state B (new with respect to the for-
mer state A) in time describes in fact the origin of "something" out of "nothing", but only,
6
of course, if the generating transcendent and immaterial principle "force", as it is nothing ma-
terial, were considered to be "nothing" at all.
2. From Newton's paradigm of origin of motion to the origin of species.
Isaac Newton introduced with his "Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica" of 1687 a
theory which was not restricted to motion only, but according to the title of his book he aimed
very generally at a new "philosophy of nature". This philosophy he meant as a counterpoint to
René Descartes' "Principia philosophiae" of 1644, which Newton understood as a false doc-
trine that misled to materialism and atheism. If one contrasts this doctrine with Newton's phi-
losophy, the main error of Descartes concerns his absolute separation of res cogitans and res
extensa, an idea that denies any interaction of spirit, soul, free will, mind etc. with the materi-
al world of extended matter only; consequently it excludes non-material entities from this
world, and thus surrenders the world to sheer materialism. If Newton was right with his suspi-
cions concerning materialism and atheism, we can clearly see today.
The general philosophical aim of Newton's teaching can be seen not only in book III of the
"Principia", where he, on the basis of his theory of motions presented in the first two books,
explains "the system of the world". Rather it is deeply rooted already in the very first princip-
les of the theory of motion. The first law of motion, for instance, as it states that every materi-
al body remains in its state of rest or uniform straightlined motion until its respective state is
changed by the action of an external "force", teaches very generally that every change in the
state of the material world requires a cause which is not iself matter, or a property of matter it-
self, but something "external" to material bodies. Matter itself is absolutely passive (16). It
changes its states only according to the actions of active external causes which cannot them-
selves be material, since matter is throughout passive. So Newton's very first law of motion
already implies the message that the generating active causes of every "change of state" in the
material world must themselves necessarily be non-material or immaterial entities in their
own right, i.e. active spiritual "forces of nature". The "generation" of change in general, then,
is described as a spirit-matter interaction, which was in Newton's time a well-known princip-
le in neo-Platonic circles such as the "Cambridge Platonists" (e.g. Ralph Cudworth, Henry
More, and Isaac Barrow, Newton's academic teacher and predecessor to the Lucasian chair of
mathematics at Cambridge University).
7
It is quite obvious that this principle must imply the origin of "species". This comes to light
e.g. in Newton's Scholium after Lemma X in the "Principia" Book I Section 1, which Scho-
lium refers to the application of geometric proportion theory in order to determine the respect-
ive quantities of "diversorum generum", that is of different species, or of different "kinds".
According to I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman: "If indeterminate quantities of different
kinds are compared with one another ..." (17).
This reference starts the question how exactly the generation of a new species according to a
spirit-matter interaction should work, or how we could mathematically describe it, if at all.
We find Newton's answer in his second law of motion, the central message of which reads as
follows: "Mutationem motus proportionalem esse vi motrici impressae" (18). That is, general-
ly spoken: Every observable change in natural material things happens in proportion to its
generating immaterial cause. Be the "change", i.e. the "effect" of the said interaction an infi-
nitely small "mutation" in the biological sense, or be it an "offspring" of a whole new "spe-
cies", that effect being symbolised by Δp, and be its generating cause, or force, or energy,
symbolised by ΔE, then we obtain the natural law of creation according to ΔE : Δp = C, with
C symbolizing the required constant of proportionality.
Evidently here begins a dualist natural philosophy of active spirit and passive matter to form
together (by interaction) the variety and the variations of the empirical world. Says Newton,
in the Scholium generale of 1713: "No variation in things arises from blind metaphysical ne-
cessity, which must be the same always and everywhere. All the diversity of created things,
each in its place and time, could only have arisen from the ideas and the will of a necessarily
existing being" (19).
All that has been said above is not only a matter of historical reminiscense, but a result of re-
search work with far-reaching consequences (not only) for the present theory of evolution.
Contrary to the general belief of evolutionists in material "mechanisms" such as mutation, se-
lection etc., Newton shows that generally "the new", and especially new species always and
only come into being as the effects of generating immaterial causes. Cardinal Schà¶nborn has
been right when he stated in 2006: Newton's philosophy of nature says about 'evolution' pre-
cisely the opposite of what scientists believe today. And Newton has also been right! The
most striking proof of this finding, however, yields the absolutely startling correspondence of
Newton's authentic principles of the theory of motion with reliable basic principles of modern
8
physics, e.g. with Einstein's equation E = mc2, and with Heisenberg's indeterminacy relations,
as I have demonstrated and published elsewhere (20).
3. Newton, the truth, and the discourse about God
Ten years ago, after having studied Pope John Paul's II enzyclic "Fides et Ratio" of 1998, I
wrote a longer German comment, which was published in the leading German Catholic jour-
nal "Mà¼nchener theologische Zeitschrift" (21). This paper "Newton, die Wahrheit und die Re-
de von Gott" I sent in the year 2000 to Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger, now Pope Benedict XVI.
He answered with great kindness, expressing his interest in my "enlightening reflexions" con-
cerning the relation of Galileo's and Newton's philosophy to the above-mentioned encyclic,
stressing his hope that my "remarkable considerations" would become a subject of "due philo-
sophical discussion" leading to a "reformation of metaphysics" (22). It must be said, however,
that theologians and philosophers in Germany have only shown the same indifference for Rat-
zinger's express hope as for most his learned writings, and especially for his criticism of
Kantian reason in the famous "prophetic" (Georg Gänswein) "Regensburg lecture" of Sep-
tember 2006 (23).
What I have shown in the above-mentioned article is the little-known aspect of Galileo's and
Newton's work as an absolutely new beginning not only of science, but of philosophy in its
very sense: a theocentric venture to prove the existence of God by analogy, i.e. by transduct-
ion from the knowledge of his reasonable creation, a scientific venture within the frame of
reference of absolute truth. Already as a student, Isaac Newton had adopted the slogan "Ami-
cus Plato amicus Aristoteles, magis amica veritas" to show that he wanted to study not in or-
der to join this or that philosophic school, but as a cooperator veritatis, a servant of truth, i.e.
of God (24).
3.1. To the 1713 second edition of the "Principia" Newton added the Scholium generale in or-
der to reveal again his general aim for a really true, i.e. realistic description, not only of a new
"theory of motion" as presented in books I and II, or a description of "the system of the
world" (book III), based on books I and II, but also of the necessary and reasonable connect-
ion of that system and its principles to the "first cause", the creator of all things. To this end,
Roger Cotes (1682-1716), at that time Plumian professor of astronomy at Cambridge, whom
Newton had chosen as editor, contributed a most interesting and elucidating "editor's preface"
to the edition.
9
Cotes begins strongly emphasizing Newton's anti-scholastic (anti-nominalistic) philosophy,
and his empirical method, by means of a methodological criticism of "those who take the
foundation of their speculations from hypotheses". Cotes continues: "Even if they then pro-
ceed most rigorously according to mechanical laws, (they) are merely putting together a ro-
mance, elegant perhaps and charming, but nevertheless a romance". After that, he explains
Newton's "twofold method, analytic and synthetic", i.e. from certain selected phenomena to
"deduce by analysis the forces of nature and the simpler laws of those forces", from which
then to "give the constitution of the rest of the phenomena by synthesis". As an example, Co-
tes uses the theory of gravity which he explains in full detail, and defends it against the con-
flicting "doctrines of Descartes", adding in favour of Newton that "it is the province of true
philosophy to derive the natures of things from causes that truly exist, and to seek those laws
by which the supreme artificer willed to establish this most beautiful order of the world, not
those laws by which he could have, had it so pleased him". Near the end of his preface, Cotes
strikes a last blow at the Cartesian theory, arguing that its adherents "finally will say that (the
constitution of the universe) has not arisen from the will of God but from some necessity of
nature. And so at last they must sink to the lowest depths of degradation, where they have the
fantasy that all things are governed by fate and not by providence, that matter has existed al-
ways and everywhere of its own necessity and is infinite and eternal.... Surely, this world, so
beautifully diversified in its forms and motions, could not have arisen except from the per-
fectly free will of God, who provides and governs all things. From this source, then, have all
the laws that are called laws of nature come, in which many traces of the highest wisdom and
counsel certainly appear, but no traces of necessity.... All sound and true philosophy is based
on phenomena, which may lead us, however unwilling and reluctant, to principles in which
the best counsel and highest dominion of an all-wise and all-powerful being are most clearly
discerned; these principles will not be rejected because certain men may perhaps not like
them. These men ... (may be) willing to confess at last that philosophy should be based on
atheism. Philosophy must not be overthrown for their sake, since the order of things refuses to
be changed".
After high praise of Newton for having "unlocked the gates", having "opened our way to the
most beautiful mysteries of nature", and having "revealed a most elegant structure of the sys-
tem of the world for our further scrutinity", Cotes concludes:
10
"And hence it is now possible to have a closer view of the majesty of nature, to enjoy the
sweetest contemplation, and to worship and venerate more zealously the maker and lord of
all; and this is by far the greatest fruit of philosophy. He must be blind who does not at once
see, from the best and wisest structures of things, the infinite wisdom and goodness of their
almighty creator; and he must be mad who refuses to acknowledge them. Therefore Newton's
excellent treatise will stand as a mighty fortress against the attacks of atheists; nowhere else
will you find more effective ammunition against that impious crowd" (25).
3.2. Newton's Scholium generale which he added to the third book of the "Principia" in 1713
is certainly the best source of his own ideas.
He begins with a short abstract of his theory of heavenly bodies in motion "according to the
laws set forth above. They will indeed persevere in their orbits by the law of gravity, but they
certainly could not originally have acquired the regular position of the orbits by these laws.....
This most elegant system of the sun, planets, and comets could not have arisen without the de-
sign and dominion of an intelligent and powerful being. And if the fixed stars are the centers
of similar systems, they will all be constructed according to a similar design and subject to the
dominion of One... And so that the systems of the fixed stars will not fall upon one another as
a result of their gravity, he has placed them at immense distances from one another. He rules
all things, not as the world soul but as the lord of all. And because of his dominion he is called
Lord God Pantokrator. For "god" is a relative word and has reference to servants, and god-
hood is the lordship of God, not over his own body as is supposed by those for whom God is
the world soul, but over servants. The supreme God is an eternal, infinite, and absolutely per-
fect being; but a being, however perfect, without dominion is not the Lord God....And from
true lordship it follows that the true God is living, intelligent, and powerful; from the other
perfections, that he is supreme, or supremely perfect. He is eternal and infinite, omnipotent
and omniscient, that is, he endures from eternity to eternity, and he is present from infinity to
infinity; he rules all things, and he knows all things that happen or can happen. He is not eter-
nity and infinity, but eternal and infinite; he is not duration and space, but he endures and is
present. He endures always and is present everywhere, and by existing always and every-
where he constitutes duration and space. Since each and every particle of space is always, and
each and every indivisible moment of duration is everywhere, certainly the maker and lord of
all things will not be never or nowhere.
11
Every sentient soul, at different times and in different organs of senses and motions, is the
same indivisible person. There are parts that are successive in duration and coexistent in spa-
ce, but neither of these exist in the person of man or in his thinking principle, and much less in
the thinking substance of God. Every man, insofar as he is a thing that has senses, is one and
the same man throughout his lifetime in each and every organ of his senses. God is one and
the same God always and everywhere. He is omnipresent not only virtually but also substanti-
ally; for active powers cannot subsist without substance. In him all things are contained and
move, but he does not act on them nor they on him. God experiences nothing from the moti-
ons of bodies; the bodies feel no resistance from God's omnipresence.
It is agreed that the supreme God necessarily exists, and by the same necessity he is always
and everywhere. It follows that all of him is like himself: he is all eye, all ear, all brain, all
arm, all force of sensing, of understanding, and of acting, but in a way not at all human, in a
way not at all corporeal, in a way utterly unknown to us. As a blind man has no idea of colors,
so we have no idea of the ways in which the most wise God senses and understands all things.
He totally lacks any body and corporeal shape, and so he cannot be seen or heard or touched,
nor ought he to be worshiped in the form of something corporeal. We have no ideas of his at-
tributes, but we certainly do not know what is the substance of any thing. We see only the
shapes and colors of bodies, we hear only their sounds, we touch only their external surfaces,
we smell only their odors, and we taste their flavors. But there is no direct sense and there are
no indirect reflected actions by which we know innermost substances; much less do we have
an idea of the substance of God. We know him only by his properties and attributes and by the
wisest and best construction of things and their final causes, and we admire him because of
his perfections; but we venerate and worship him because of his dominion. For we worship
him as servants, and a god without dominion, providence, and final causes is nothing other
than fate and nature. No variation in things arises from blind metaphysical necessity, which
must be the same always and everywhere. All the diversity of created things, each in its place
and time, could only have arisen from the ideas and the will of a necessarily existing being.
But God is said allegorically to see, hear, speak, laugh, love, hate, desire, give, receive, re-
joice, be angry, fight, build, form, construct. For all discourse about God is derived through a
certain similitude from things human, which while not perfect is nevertheless a similitude of
some kind. This concludes the discussion of God, and to treat of God from phenomena is cer-
tainly a part of natural philosophy...." (26).
12
There exists another revealing passage on natural philosophy to be found in Newton's "Op-
ticks", at the end of "Query 31", after some methodological considerations. Here Newton
shows his philosophy, if correctly understood as a theocentric research of truth, to provide
the generating source of a progress of human ethics, or "moral philosophy". The passage
reads as follows:
"... And if Natural Philosophy in all its parts, by pursuing this method, shall at length be
perfected, the bounds of Moral Philosophy will also be enlarged. For so far as we can know
by Natural philosophy what is the First cause, what power he has over us, and what benefits
we receive from him, so far our duty towards him, as well as that towards one another, will
appear to us by the light of Nature" (27).
_________________________________________________________________________
Footnotes
(1) See Creation and Evolution, A Conference with Pope Benedict XVI. in Castel Gandolfo,
Ignatius Press San Francisco 2008, p. 84-106; German edition: Schà¶pfung und Evolution, Ei-
ne Tagung mit Papst Benedikt XVI. in Castel Gandolfo, Augsburg 2007, S. 79-98.
(2) Cf. Schà¶nborn's footnote 1. However, in his, German! - Castel Gandolfo talk the Car-
dinal did not quote from the English Motte-Cajori edition of Newton's Principia, as he asserts
here, but rather he quoted from my selected German edition (Isaac Newton, Mathematische
Grundlagen der Naturphilosophie, Ed Dellian ed., Hamburg 1988, the first and only reliable
and qualified German "Principia" to appear 300 years after Newton's first (1687) edition. For
this cf. the German edition of Schà¶nborn's talk, as cited in footnote 1) above. Meanwhile, a
second edition of my selected Principia translation has been published by Academia Verlag
Sankt Augustin, 2007.
(3) "Deum summum necessario existere in confesso est". I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whit-
man have translated this phrase as follows: "It is agreed that the supreme God necessarily ex-
ists". See Isaac Newton, the Principia, Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy, A
New Translation by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman, Preceded by A Guide to Newton's
Principia, by I. Bernard Cohen, Berkeley-Los Angeles-London, 1999, p. 942.
(4) Isaac Newton, Principia, 2nd ed. 1713, Book III, Scholium generale. I quote this English
version from Cardinal Schà¶nborn.
(5) See Creation and Evolution as quoted in fn. 1 above, p. 89 fn. 5. Meanwhile my book has
been published in an extended version: Ed Dellian, "Die Rehabilitierung des Galileo Galilei
oder Kritik der Kantischen Vernunft" (The 'Rehabilitation of Galileo Galilei or a Criticism of
Kantian Reason'), Sankt Augustin 2007.
(6) In the Scholium generale Newton writes: "Et haec de Deo, de quo utique ex Phaenomenis
disserere ad Philosophiam Naturalem pertinet." That is: "To treat of God from phenomena is
certainly a part of 'natural' philosophy" (Cohen-Whitman p. 943).
13
(7) See e.g. Colin Maclaurin, An Account of Sir Isaac Newton's Philosophical Discoveries,
London 1748, p. 55.
(8) See Cohen-Whitman p. 437/8, where Newton's Lemma X concerning the generation of
motion reads: "The spaces which a body describes when urged by any finite force,... are at
the very beginning of the motion in the squared ratio of the times."
(9) Newton's words in the explanation to his second law of motion are: "Si vis aliqua motum
quemvis generet, dupla duplum, tripla triplum generabit, sive simul et semel, sive gradatim et
successive impressa fuerit." According to Cohen-Whitman: "If some force generates any mot-
ion, twice the force will generate twice the motion, and three times the force will generate
three times the motion, whether the force is impressed all at once or successively by degrees"
(p. 416).
(10) Newton opens the "Third Book" of the Principia with three "regulae philosophandi" (Co-
hen-Whitman: "Rules for the study of natural philosophy"). There he writes: "Certe contra ex-
perimentorum tenorem somnia temere confingenda non sunt, nec a Naturae analogia receden-
dum est, cum ea simplex esse soleat et sibi semper consona." According to Cohen-Whitman:
"Certainly idle fancies ought not to be fabricated recklessly against the evidence of experi-
ments, nor should we depart from the analogy of nature, since nature is always simple and
ever consonant with itself" (p. 795).
(11) Paolo Casini, Newton's Principia and the philosophers of the Enlightenment, in: New-
on's Principia and its Legacy, D.G. King-Hele and A.R. Hall eds., London (The Royal Socie-
ty) 1988, p. 48.
(12) In Newton's 1686 preface to the Principia one reads, in Cohen-Whitman's English:
"The basic problem [lit. Omnis enim difficultas, i.e. the whole difficulty] of philosophy seems
to be to discover the forces of nature from the phenomena of motions and then to demonstrate
the other phenomena from these forces" (p. 382).
(13) Cohen-Whitman p. 424.
(14) Already in Galileo's "Discorsi" of 1638 the increasing velocity of free fall is described as
a successive step-by-step augmentation of generated discrete units of velocity to the already
established sum of such units. Contrary to this view, classical mechanics, following not Gali-
leo and Newton but Descartes and Leibniz, teaches a continuous augmentation of velocity.
The authentic Galileian-Newtonian theory then appears as a quantum theory of motion, with
far-reaching consequences not only for the history of science, but also for the understanding
of "modern physics". For this see Ed Dellian, "Die Rehabilitierung des Galileo Galilei oder
Kritik der Kantischen Vernunft", as quoted in footnote 5 above, and the introduction to my
Principia-edition of 2007, as quoted in footnote 2 above.
(15) Of course it contradicts classical mechanics absolutely to state that there should not exist
a continuously accelerating force. Is not such a force the generally accepted cause of gravita-
tional motion? Nevertheless, if one reads Newton carefully, one sees that the continuous (and
consequently infinite) force of gravity is not the immediate cause of motion. Rather Newton
describes it as kind of a source of finite forces, or quantities, or quanta of forces, the "vires
impressae", which produce proportional finite quantities of motion stepwise. Cf. Principia,
Newton's explanation to Def. 4 (Cohen-Whitman p. 405). Referring to circular motion around
14
a centre, Newton demonstrates this fact even to the eye, in Principia, Book I Section 2 Propo-
sition 1 Theorem 1 (see Cohen-Whitman p. 444).
(16) That matter was passive, and could only be forced to change its state by external immate-
rial causes or "forces", was common knowledge of neo-platonic Renaissance scholars (Gali-
leo, Torricelli, Boyle etc.). Newton is very clear about this in his "Opticks", Query 31.
(17) Cohen-Whitman p. 438.
(18) According to Cohen-Whitman: "A change in motion is proportional to the motive force
impressed ..." (p. 416).
(19) Cohen-Whitman p. 942.
(20) Cf. e.g. my published papers as follows: 1) Die Newtonische Konstante, Philos. Nat. vol.
22 no. 3 (1985) p. 400; 2) Experimental philosophy reappraised, Spec.Sci.Techn. vol. 9 no. 2
(1986) p. 135; 3) Inertia, the Innate Force of Matter, a Legacy from Newton to Modern Phy-
sics, in: P.B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds.), Newton's Scientific and Philosophical Legacy,
Arch. Internat. Hist. Idées no. 23 (1988), Dordrecht (Kluwer), p. 227; 4) On Cause and Effect
in Quantum Physics, Spec. Sci. Techn. vol. 12 no. 1 (1989) p. 45; 5) Newton, die Trägheits-
kraft und die absolute Bewegung, Philos. Nat. vol. 26 no. 2 (1989) p. 34; 6) Does Quantum
Mechanics Imply the Concept of Impetus? Physics Essays vol. 3 no. 4 (1990) p. 365; 7) Neu-
es à¼ber die Erkenntnistheorie Isaac Newtons, Zeitschr. f. philos. Forschung 1992 no. 1 p. 89;
8) Newton, die Wahrheit und die Rede von Gott, Zur Enzyklika ~Fides et Ratio" Papst Johan-
nes Paul II., Mà¼nchener theolog. Zeitschr. vol. 51 (2000) no. 2 p. 171; 9) Newton on Mass
and Force, Physics Essays vol. 16 (2003) no. 2., Some more articles can be found on my
website http://www.neutonus-reformatus.de .
21) See footnote (20), no. 8).
22) Joseph Cardinal Ratzinger, private letter to the author, Oct. 25, 2000.
23) Cf. Christoph Dohmen (ed.), Die 'Regensburger Vorlesung' Papst Benedikts XVI. im
Dialog der Wissenschaften, Regensburg 2007. On p. 112 Gereon Piller states that the Pope as
an intellectual, insofar as he derives his zeitgeist criticism from the vanishing worship of God,
is fighting all over Europe utterly alone ("europaweit allein auf weiter Flur").
24) For the slogan "Amicus Plato ..." see Richard S. Westfall, Never at Rest, A Biography of
Isaac Newton, Cambridge 1980, p. 89.
25) All quotations of Cotes from I. Bernard Cohen's and Anne Whitman's Principia edition,
pp. 385-398.
26) I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman, pp. 939-943.
27) Isaac Newton, Opera quae exstant omnia, Samuel Horsley ed., London 1779-1785, vol. 4
p. 264.

Ed Dellian, D-14169 Berlin, Bogenst. 5, Tel./Fax 0049-030-84714564, http://www.neutonus-reformatus.de________________________________________________________________
 
arg-fallbackName="Cygnus"/>
From what I read, it's basically a giant appeal to the personal beliefs of Newton(the result of lacking modern science), with lots of weighted words thrown in to sway people into accepting the author as an authority figure.

Oh, and Newton was wrong. A little known German-American physicist did some pretty amazing work to improve upon Newton's ideas. So it might not be the best idea to use Newton's centuries old ideas as an argument against science.
 
Back
Top